All Things Shining Part II

He deals the cards as a meditation

And those he plays never suspect

He doesn’t play for the money he wins

He don’t play for respect

 

He deals the cards to find the answer

The sacred geometry of chance

The hidden law of a probable outcome

The numbers lead a dance

 

– Shape of My Heart, Sting

So, even after skipping to the final chapter and registering my initial thoughts on this site (see below my post “Initial Thoughts on ‘All Things Shining’”), I went back to the other chapters and finished reading the book (yep, I actually did). Doing so gave me a lot more context on where the authors are coming from and simultaneously served as an organized introduction to some philosophers and literature pieces I knew little or nothing about.

Grossly oversimplifying, their main point, as I understand it, is that there are opportunities to experience the sacred in a Godless world. There is no need to believe in a God (or Gods) to do so, only the predisposition to perceive and experience “moods” in the world around us, be part of those moods that come and go like a wave (“whoosh”) and nurture our capacity to do so like an artisan nurture’s its craft. They contrast their view with that of other philosophers and writers, briefly describing a history of western thought that evolved from a polytheist experience of “moods,” such as those in Homer’s work, to a more monotheistic type worldview in classical Greece, and then through two paradigm shifts (Jesus Christ and Christianity and the Enlightenment and Renee Descartes) that gradually brought us to a nihilist reality, centered on the self-sufficient individual (I find my own pretense of summarizing much of a book in one paragraph astonishing, but…there it is!). For my own benefit, I attempted to organize my understanding of their portrayal of this history of philosophy in Figure 1 below (including a few of my unresolved questions).

Figure 1 – Notes that likely only I am able to follow


There seems to be: a)  an essential assumption in the authors’ reasoning, and b) an essential observation.

The assumption is that meaning is to be found outside of ourselves. We cannot successfully impose it. They make this argument in the second chapter of the book, when discussing David Foster Wallace’s Nihilism and his proposition that we can impose meaning on our reality. They state this possibility is “the most demanding and the most impoverished all at once” (p 47):

  • Most demanding because:
    • It raises the stakes for happiness and demands a kind of bliss that supersedes any kind of earthly condition (ps. 47-48). They later equate this with the Buddhist concept of Nirvana (see ps 163-164).
    • It demands that bliss be constant and achieved at all times (p. 48)
  • Impoverished because there is no place for gratitude (p.48)

They reject this option as a source of meaning and re-emphasize on several occasions throughout the book. For example, on p 142: “The history of the last 150 years suggests that we are not the proper source for meaning in the world”

I, quite frankly, don’t see how they deduce any of the points above. The fact that they seem convinced that they have made their case and discuss the rest of the book as if meaning must be found outside the self, to me, unfortunately, weakens the entire book that, otherwise, I find very interesting, illuminating even. To top it off, as mentioned in my previous post below, they take the cheap shot of using the example of David Foster Wallace’s suicide to emphasize that this is the only possible ending. Thinking back, if all this had sunk in while I was reading the book, I probably would have stopped right there. But I am glad that I continued reading and can enjoy the rest of the book by thinking of the above as an assumption made by the authors, not something they were really set to demonstrate. I can live with that and address the assumption elsewhere.

The observation I can easily agree with. The observation is that we cannot control everything that happens outside of ourselves. We do not fully control our world and the events that surround us. This seems to me to be patently and observably true. It is even arguable that we do not control everything about ourselves (such as quick, intuitive thinking, and involuntarily biological processes).

Given the “assumption” and the “observation” (by the way, these designations are mine, not the authors’), this leads them through a path of wanting to be in-sync with, immersed in, aware of this uncontrolled and uncontrollable environment, and the external “moods” that are generated with the idea that, in doing so, we generate an opportunity to experience meaning, something we can call sacred. I see the appeal of this way of thinking and I see parallels with oriental philosophy that, for some reason the authors seem to want to negate.

Now here is where my thoughts go next: what if we look at the whooshing, the moods, the physis we are exposed to as being generated by random events? We can even choose to look at our own choices and the choices of those around us as generated by random events or being individual outcomes of random events (leaving aside the fact that, in that case, we probably wouldn’t discuss them as “choices”). If we think about the examples the author’s give in these terms, how would our outlook on meaning differ?

To use one of the author’s examples, say we are at a sporting event and collectively experience an athlete “in the zone.” We all realize what is happening and collectively feel we have been a part of something special. For this special moment to occur, we need to have gone to the sporting event, and we need to have been open to experience the athlete’s performance as something special. In addition, those around us need to have done so as well, and at least one athlete must have been “in the zone” on that day. We can look at the aspects of this experience that we do not control as random events: the choices and behaviors of others attending the game, and the likelihood that at least one athlete will be “in the zone.” In that case, our special experience, our experience of the “sacred,” would be one possible outcome of a joint probability distribution of the random events we are exposed to. Why is there a stronger argument to feel gratitude in this case, then in any other outcome of the joint distribution?

In the end, it seems to me what really matters is what the authors’ assumed away in the first two chapters of the book: whether meaning can be attributed from within, whether it needs to be defined in relation to something outside ourselves, and whether meaning should be attributed at all, at least if we look at the world as one that can be described by joint distributions of random events. It is as if the author’s efforts to propose an alternative to today’s nihilism relies on first simply assuming away nihilism as a viable outlook on life. It seems to me the central question is to what extent we think of what we experience in the world as being random or deterministic.

The discussion above takes me to a memory of my father. My father was an engineer. He was very intelligent and liked math. He was also very Catholic. I have this recollection of a period when he was logging into a table the results of the national lottery where he lived. The idea was that, perhaps, he could find a pattern in the lottery numbers. A pattern that would maybe signal some higher order or something he could be “in-sync” with, tuned into. I am sure he would have liked to win the lottery, and he would have interpreted it as a gift from God. Many Catholics view the world as a place where everything happens for a reason. But I honestly think that the discovery of a pattern itself would have been way more rewarding to him than any payments he would have received from winning the lottery. It would have proven the existence of a higher order and at the same time provided some personal intellectual gratification. It is possible to think of my father’s attempt, and it seems to me of the entire book discussed above, as ultimately stemming from a kind of wishful thinking. One that is not unappealing to me, yet difficult for me to accept. One that is difficult for me to accept, yet not unappealing to me.

I don’t think my father knew much statistics, or perhaps didn’t care much for it. And, spoiler alert, to my knowledge he never found a pattern in the lottery numbers, or at least not one that proved successful in winning the national lottery. Interestingly enough, he did many years later win a car in a lottery from the club he belonged to: it was close to Christmas time and he did quite desperately need a new car. He interpreted it as a gift, perhaps even as a reward for his faith, and I am sure he was thankful. Relevant to the discussion above: he did not pick the numbers.

Reference:

Dreyfus, Hubert and Sean Dorrance Kelly. 2011. All Things Shining. Reading the Western Classics to Find Meaning in a Secular Age. New York: Free Press.

Continue ReadingAll Things Shining Part II

Initial Thoughts on “All Things Shining”

I started reading “All Things Shining: Reading the Western Classics to Find Meaning in a Secular Age,” by philosophy professors Herbert Dreyfus (Berkeley) and Sean Dorrance Kelly (Harvard). At the end of the second chapter, after using authors David Foster Wallace and Elizabeth Gilbert to illustrate contrasting views on how meaning is generated or attributed in our daily lives, they end with the following paragraph:

“The question that remains is whether Gilbert and Wallace between them have completely covered the terrain. In Wallace’s Nietschean view, we are the sole active agents in the universe, responsible for generating out of nothing whatever notion of the sacred and divine there can ever be. Gilbert, by contrast, takes a kind of mature Lutheran view. On her account we are purely passive recipients of God’s divine will, nothing but receptacles for the grace he may choose to offer. Is there anything in between? We think there is, and we will try to develop it in the final chapter of the book.” (p. 57)

Needless to say, I skipped to the final chapter.

In that chapter they suggest there is present, today, in our culture, opportunities to generate a kind of experience where, we neither need to impose meaning on our world, nor passively await for meaning to descend upon our lives.

They start by suggesting that there are often collective experiences of marvel, bliss, exhultation. Experiences like those where expectators attending a live sporting event witness an athlete “in the zone” and are collectively taken by the experience. Or when, also collectively, we rejoice in a skilled orator’s speech. They equate these experiences with moments of realization of Homer’s notion of physis: how the world is in as much as it presents itself to us. They also suggest the exhultation of these collective experiences come and go as a wave. They use the term “whoosh” to describe it.

They then recognize the dangers of “whooshing,” like when the collective experience is dominated by some type of mass mentality and pack behavior, and where rational self-control is obliterated.

But they claim there is another type of experience available to us, which also offers an opportunity for experiencing meaning in our physical connection to the world, and which, in addition, can be used to discern between “good” and “bad” whooshing. They equate that experience with the Aristotelian term: poiesis. Poiesis captures a craftsman’s like practice of developing an intimate understanding and relationship with some aspect of our world. A relationship characterized by a “feedback loop between craftsman and craft” (p.211) and through which meaning also arises.

But “poiesis” too has its limitations, in that, in our world, it is under attack by technology. Technology that reduced our need to deeply understand our world to reach our goals. An example they give is that of GPS, through which we can move from one place to another, simply by following orders, and with never building significant knowledge of our surroundings.

The authors then argue that it is up to us to discover, in what we already care about, the opportunities for poiesis. Whether it is in drinking a cup of coffee in the morning, enjoying a walk, or the company of a friend. In other words, discovering it in our relationship to the world, and then nurturing it, transforming routine into ritual. They argue that is the realm of the sacred that exists currently in our world: a rich polytheistic world where the sacred manifests itself through physis and poiesis, and where technology has its place, without completely erasing the opportunities for the sacred.

I am very much enjoying the book, and intend to read the chapters in between (really…at some point), but here are a few thoughts based on the three chapters I read already:

  • In trying to describe how we can discover what we care about and build rituals around routines to nourish our experience of being in this world through poiesis, they use the example of having coffee each morning. They suggest asking what we like about this routine, whether it is the warmth of the coffee, the striking black color, the aroma. That is, they appeal to the senses. This appeal to the senses is very similar to how I have learned to practice mindfulness, to be present in this world, based on my understanding of the practice and the teachings of Thich Naht Hahn. Other parallels to eastern ways of thinking could be made when discussing Wallace’s “This is Water” commencement speech in chapter two. Yet, the authors do not seem to be interested in discussing these potential parallels, at least not in the parts I have read.
  • In discussing Wallace’s nihilism, they propose that, to the extent that he can see any space for the sacred, his attempt to reach it is by imposing meaning on experience, creating this meaning out of nothing, and constantly doing so. There are no constraints on the meaning Wallace can impose on his experience. They suggest this self-imposed task is not humanly possible. In fact, they state that “in such a world, as Melville understood, grim perseverance is possible for a while; but in the end suicide is the only choice” (p.50). I a) do not see how or why “suicide is the only choice,” and b) find this statement actually in bad taste, to say the least, since Wallace did commit suicide. His example is rather an unfairly picked choice, unnecessarily making use of someone’s suicide to make their argument.
  • The authors describe Wallace and Gilbert as having a similar view of the purpose of writing: translating life, conveying what it means to be human, becoming less alone. If the interpretation of our world and our condition is actually an intrinsic and inseparable part of our human condition, one could argue that storytelling is not just interpreting what it means to be human, but actually contributing to creating that condition. Storytelling would then be a way of creating rather than just interpreting our world. I have for a while found this way of thinking appealing, and it is different from what the authors claim to be the views of Wallace and Gilbert. It is perhaps more in tune with Mario Vargas Llosa’s story in his book “El Hablador.” Perhaps something I will explore further in the future.

Reference:

Dreyfus, Hubert and Sean Dorrance Kelly. 2011. All Things Shining. Reading the Western Classics to Find Meaning in a Secular Age. New York: Free Press.

Continue ReadingInitial Thoughts on “All Things Shining”

End of content

No more pages to load